Thursday, April 6, 2017

Book review. Appiah K.A. "Cosmopolitanism: Ethics in the world of strangers"

The book “Cosmopolitanism: Ethics in the world of strangers” was written by Kwame Anthony Appiah (2006), British philosopher of Ghanaian origin with roots in Asante ethnic group, but primarily human being and cosmopolitan person. The work of prominent in the field of cosmopolitanism author, comprises a range of disciplines as well as Appiah’s personal experience to build a main argument that cosmopolitanism is the philosophy, ideology and, as written on the back cover of his book, a “moral manifesto for a planet of strangers” who need to live together. Ten chapters of the book complemented by introduction present an insightful and engaging reading for the scholars as well as for sophisticated readers who are accustomed with philosophical school of thought. Author builds his work drawing a general picture of what is the cosmopolitanism referring to influential thinkers as well as examples from literature and history. In the next chapters, he proceeds to outline his philosophical position, illustrate fallacies of other schools of thought and continues by giving us a practical approach towards understanding, living and collaboration with people inhabiting our planet. Appiah also brings to attention a set of responsibilities which we share as human beings.
The main argument of the book is an appeal to humanity to take a responsible stance over our relations with varying strangers coming from different parts of the planet and sharing diverse beliefs and values. It is Appiah’s urge to take a stance of cosmopolitanism as the driving philosophy and ethical way of living. Author is sure that “cosmopolitanism is an adventure and an ideal” (p. xviii) and, at the same time, “there’s a sense in which cosmopolitanism is the name not of the solution but of the challenge” (p. xiii). Indeed, the book defined by Kofi Annan as “the great human project of trying to live together” needs a solid philosophical stance and moreover it should be a practical and manageable motivation for action. Kwame Anthony Appiah is not a slave of illusions and he believes that “we need to develop habits of coexistence: conversation [emphasis added] in its older meaning, of living together, association” (p. xvii). But how do we approach this conversation? Appiah believes that the dialogue from positivist and relativist positions is circled to not bring us to final destination. For instance, he suggests that the cornerstone of positivists thinking, namely rationale, fails when labeling our values as true or false (p. 22). Appiah proposes that even if such universal values as kindness or humanness cannot be rationally justified, they still make sense to us and we still value them (p. 21). Indeed, Appiah’s concern about vision of the world in black and white colors, labeled as true or false has to be demolished by scholars again and again as a remnant of the past which does not make sense today. Yet another extreme – relativism (p. 31) – has nothing to offer for conversation of strangers as it denies any objectivity of values, certain universal agreements which are valued by the whole humankind.
Appiah develops his argument of the need for thoughtful conversation throughout the chapters of the book. It should be said that he proposes a kind of guide to enter this interaction. To begin with, author states that “we enter every conversation … without a promise of final agreement” (p. 44). It is reality and this should not stop us from making this conversation happen. It is always easy to say that someone is not possible to convince, however even if the dialogue is not about consensus it may be about understanding of positions. Appiah’s second argument is that even if we do not take values of our interlocutors seriously we are able to listen and understand why they make sense to them (p. 56). Putting it simply, the conversation – in Appiah’s position it is not limited to physical presence but is about “engagement with the experience and the ideas of others” (p. 85) – in which people are trying to understand one another may be a first step for them “to get used to another” (p. 85). As a result, distant strangers are no more strangers for us but people we know. Third, Appiah talks about the language of conversation itself. When the dispute may have the same vocabulary of values, it does not guarantee us that we share the same criteria of their evaluation, interpretations and degree of importance (p. 67). This is to say that even universal from a first look values may be rooted into local context differently. As a solution, author comes to the main from my perspective conclusions “we can agree about what to do even when we don’t agree why” (p. 67) and “we can live together without agreeing on what the values are that make it good to live together” (p. 71). Indeed, if in our conversation we are trying to stick to these powerful insights, we may find ourselves far beyond those who share different understanding of the dialogue. Finally, Appiah stipulates that we as human beings have a lot in common and are connected to one another “despite difference” (p. 135).  Rationally or not, we have certain obligations to strangers, as put by Appiah “we owe to others” (p. 165), and we are responsible to contribute feasible efforts (p. 164) to sustain basic needs every human being has (p. 163). By saying this, author concludes his appeal to cosmopolitanism leaving us with many answers, questions and, at the same time, actions to do.
This reading highly resonates with my perception of the word and surely adds many perspectives for my order of though on this matter. I see many connections to what I have read during my course of studies as well as connections to my research project in the process. For example, I find that writers whose readings fascinate me the most do talk about certain concepts in the similar way. Appiah mentions Adam Smith (2002) who states that there is no guarantee that strangers “have the same grip on our sympathies” (p. 158) and we cannot “demand” (p. 158) them to have. The word “demand” simultaneously triggered me to think about Nel Nodding’s philosophy of care where she acknowledges that when we care about someone we do not wait or do it to receive response. From my perspective, cosmopolitanism may theoretically benefit taking ideas of caring relations in conversation it is talking about. Yet another sentence which caught my attention is Appiah’s reflections on the nature of culture: “we do not need, have never needed, settled community, a homogeneous system of values, in order to have a home. Cultural purity is an oxymoron” (p. 113). Similarly, Pieterse (2015) talks about “cultural differentialism” (p. 42) and “cultural convergence” (p. 42) as opposed to “cultural hybridization” (p. 42). I find that authors correlate in their position that neither emphasizing difference neither stressing homogeneity does not move us closer to conversation capable to bring shared understanding. We may also find an inference to United Nations Educational Scientific and Cultural Organization’s (2017) call for “building a sense of belonging to a common humanity” (para. 1). Not surprising that many powerful thinkers and recognizable organizations take for ideological basis what cosmopolitanism talks about. In turn, when making connections to my research project, I should acknowledge that the philosophical position of cosmopolitanism may offer me a more comprehensive picture of the reality and our social role inside of it. For example, when it is easy to apply the theory of the knowledge based economy for the notion of the 21st century skills, which I use in my thesis, I would better think about turning it into the discourse of human rights and creation of cosmopolite identities through the mean of education.
In conclusion, the book of Kwame Anthony Appiah (2006) is certainly kind of a desk book which talks about complex issues simply. Complemented by sound philosophical discussion, it presents a practical claim for action to start a conversation between people from cosmopolitan position of thought. Appiah builds his argument around necessity of this conversation when stressing the importance of mutual understanding and recognition of obligations which “we owe” (p. 165) to humanity. This book widens the horizons of thinking and presents us alternatives we did not know before. I find this book highly relevant to my dissertation and intent to use it as a moral reference in my research activities. Jason’s future students might find this interesting given its relevance to our course themes and topics. For example, Appiah’s book comprises the most appealing to the problems of humanity concepts and puts them into one theory of cosmopolitanism capable to bring the question of morale into the matter of education in relation to globalization.
References
Appiah, K. A. (2006). Cosmopolitanism: Ethics in the world of strangers. England: Penguin Books.
Noddings, N. (2012). Philosophy of education (3 ed.). Westview Press.
Pieterse, J. N. (2015). Globalization and culture: Three paradigms. In J. N. Pieterse, Globalization and culture: Global mélange (pp. 41-58). USA: Rowman & Littlefield.
Smith, A. (2002). The theory of moral sentiments. (K. Haakonssen, Ed.) Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

UNESCO. (2017). Global Citizenship Education. Retrieved March 12, 2017, from WWW.UNESCO.ORG: http://en.unesco.org/gced/approach